Skip to main content
  • Research article
  • Open access
  • Published:

What do you mean by “palliative sedation”?

Pre-explicative analyses as preliminary steps towards better definitions

Abstract

Background

Sedation in palliative care is frequently but controversially discussed. Heterogeneous definitions and conceptual confusion have been cited as contributing to different problems 1) relevant to empirical research, for example, inconsistent data about practice, the ‘data problem’, and 2) relevant for an ethically legitimate characterisation of the practice, the ‘problem of ethical pre-emption’. However, little is known about how exactly definitions differ, how they cause confusion and how this can be overcome.

Method

Pre-explicative analyses: (A) systematic literature search for guidelines on sedation in palliative care and systematic decomposition of the definitions of the practice in these guidelines; (B) logical distinction of different ways through which the two problems reported might be caused by definitions; and (C) analysis of how content of the definitions contributes to the problems reported in these different ways.

Results

29 guidelines from 14 countries were identified. Definitions differ significantly in both structure and content. We identified three ways in which definitions can cause the ‘data problem’ – 1) different definitions, 2) deviating implicit concepts, 3) disagreement about facts. We identified two ways to cause the problem of ethical pre-emption: 1) explicit or 2) implicit normativity. Decomposition of definitions linked to the distinguished ways of causing the conceptual problems shows how exactly single parts of definitions can cause the problems identified.

Conclusion

Current challenges concerning empirical research on sedation in palliative care can be remediated partly by improved definitions in the future, if content and structure of the used definitions is chosen systematically. In addition, future research should bear in mind that there are distinct purposes of definitions. Regarding the ‘data problem’, improving definitions is possible in terms of supplementary information, checking for implicit understanding, systematic choice of definitional elements. ‘Ethical pre-emption’, in contrast, is a pseudo problem if definitions and the relationship of definitions and norms of good practice are understood correctly.

Peer Review reports

Background

Sedation in palliative care is frequently and, simultaneously, controversially discussed, for example, regarding the indication, safety or justification compared to other end-of-life measures [14].

Good practice, research and fruitful discussion often depend on good and comprehensible terms. The problem with defining sedation practices and the existence of heterogeneous definitions has been criticised repeatedly in the light of associated problems relevant for good practice and research [58].

One problem which has been raised repeatedly in this context is that of inconsistent empirical data. It has been observed that there is an unexplained variation concerning the frequency of sedation in palliative care practice [9, p. 427], [10, p. 5], [11]. The vagueness of definitions and their variety are considered as contributing causes for this [9, 12], [13], [p. 2, 6].

In addition to this ‘data problem’, there is a second problem reported to be connected with definitions, which we call the ‘problem of ethical pre-emption’: Authors have argued [6, 14] that sedation is an ethically controversial procedure in palliative care. They criticise that moral discourse is decided beforehand (‘pre-empted’) when practices are defined as “therapy” or “ethically acceptable”, as it is the case in the well-known European Association for Palliative Care (EAPC) definition [15]. It has been suggested that exclusion of controversial cases of sedation by means of definitions produces a lack of transparency and open discussion and, consequently, a lack of a search for improvement [14].

While both the ‘data problem’ and the ‘problem of ethical pre-emption’ are alleged to have their roots in terminology, to the best of our knowledge, there has never been an analysis of how exactly definitions of ‘palliative sedation’ and similar terms cause these problems. In addition, there is a lack of rigorous conceptual analysis of existing definitions by which deficits could be identified and could pave the way for the improvement of definitions.

With this paper, we aim at supporting the comprehension of the terminological confusion, the resulting empirical and ethical problems and at developing strategies for creating clearer definitions that avoid the problems reported as much as possible. We tried to answer three questions to provide these analyses and tools for better definitions: (A) How exactly do definitions of sedation practices in palliative care differ? (B) How might definitions (logically) contribute to the data and ethical pre-emption problem? (C) How does definitional content contribute plausibly to the data or pre-emption problem regarding the ways identified?

Methods

If any technical term is not shaped in an entirely novel way but explicitly also according to expressions that are already being used, then this process of term construction is called “explication” in theory of science [1618] Given the heterogeneous and vague use of terms like “palliative sedation”, there is a need of such an explication.

It is standard to distinguish different steps in the explicatory procedure and to begin with preliminary steps in the literature on concept explication: discussing synonymy and ambiguity. These clarifications have also been called “pre-explicative procedures” [19]. Synonyms of “palliative sedation” and their pros and cons have been listed by others [6]. Our work focuses on the ambiguity problem by answering the three aforementioned questions (A)–(C). For this purpose we used different methods:

(A) To answer the question how definitions differ exactly, we conducted a systematic literature search (A 1) and extracted definitions and deconstructed them (A 2).

(A1) We focused on guideline definitions based on the assumptions that these have great impact and support in the respective community and have also been chosen thoughtfully. We conducted a systematic review following the PRISMA guideline [20] to identify relevant guidelines and searched the following databases: Medline, Cinahl, Embase, Psycinfo, Cochrane Library, Scopus and Web of Science up to 11 December 2019 (for Medline search string see Table 1). Additionally, we performed a web search via Google with a standardised search string and a search on selected websites for international medical literature and guidelines (Tripdatabase, Gin, Epistemonikos, AHRQ, Nice). Search terms were in English. There were no restrictions on publication language. We screened the reference lists of guidelines included and identified systematic reviews for other documents. We screened the first 200 search results when it was not possible to use a search syntax. We included national, regional or institutional guidelines with a focus on sedation in palliative care. We then excluded publications without institutional or regional/national legitimization and those with a broader focus (i.e. intensive care, end-of-life care in general). We searched for updated versions on the institutions’ websites and only included the latest versions. We included only original documents or our own translations when possible. We excluded publications with a broader focus (i.e. intensive care, end-of-life care in general). Each screening and data extraction was performed by the main author and a researcher assistant individually. Regarding the publications included, we extracted definitions and translated them if necessary, assisted by at least one native-speaking colleague with a medical background. We did not perform a formal quality assessment of the guidelines included, for example, with AGREE II [21].

Table 1 Search String (Medline)

(A2) We then deconstructed the definitions. Sedation in palliative care is a medical practice. As there is no standard for definitional elements of practices, we used the following analytical categories to deconstruct the definitions: action, means, object, purpose, intended path of action, unintended consequence (see Table 2). These categories are influenced by the 20th century philosophy of action, for example [22], and are applicable to all practices on a very basic level.

Table 2 Categories for analysis of elements of sedation definitions

The category “explicit moral property” was added to the categories to display where the “normativity” criticised in the argument against ‘ethical pre-emption’ was explicitly present in the definition. We tested categories until we achieved “analytical saturation”, in the sense that definitions could be fully deconstructed. More fine-grained categories are possible but can be seen as subcategories of the ones we used.

(B) Answering the question how exactly definitions cause the ‘data problem’ and the ‘problem of ethical pre-emption’ requires preparatory thought. Starting from the description of the two problems allegedly caused by problematic definitions – the ‘data problem’ and the ‘problem of ethical pre-emption’ – we performed a logical analysis of how exactly the problems might be caused by definitions. Our approach is based on standards on the theory of definition [23].

(C) To answer how specific definitional content can cause the data or pre-emption problem, we linked the results of (A) to distinctions made concerning topic (B). For each of the definitional categories, we discussed how it might contribute to the ‘data problem’ and the ‘problem of ethical pre-emption’ in the ways distinguished in (B).

Results

(A) systematic search for guideline definitions and decomposition

We included 31 publications. Most publications are from Europe or the US/Canada. One publication is from Japan and one from Australia and New Zealand. The guidelines are mostly authored by national palliative care societies in Europe, or more regional palliative care programs in the US and Canada. Two publications are authored by European medical societies. See Table 3 (See Additional file 3 for the landscape format of the Table). One guideline [52] did not have any identifiable definition. Authors of one other guideline are indecisive about the terminology [53]. We excluded these publications, leaving 29 publications for from further analysis. Also, we found a newer guideline from Japan [54] that is available in Japanese only and used the older translation by [50] because of that.

Table 3 Extracted definitions with deconstruction of content, sorted by year of publication (* = our translation)

We had problems with extracting definitions. The sentences we extracted were not marked as a definition in some guidelines [15, 26, 31, 35, 36, 38, 40], leaving it to the reader whether to take them as full-fledged definitions. In some cases it was not clear where the authors intended their definition to end [4043, 47]. This was problematic, especially when several sentences are given after a headline “definition” that might not all belong to the definition [40, 43, 47, 51]. A further challenge to identify definitions was inconsistent reference from one guideline to another regarding definition. A guideline from France, for example, referred to a definition in an older French guideline, but the translation and the original differ significantly (cf. [25] and [45]). Two guidelines from Italian medical societies published in 2007 (cf. [47] and [48]) lso give different definitions, though they might have been intended as verbal translations of each other. The guideline from Austria refers to the EAPC definition but does not translate it precisely (cf. [31] and [15]). The term to be defined varied slightly. “Palliative sedation” was used most frequently, sometimes stated with a synonym, for example, “therapeutic sedation”. Table 3 shows all the definitions and content for each category. Please note that the same category can be used with a different content. We will summarise the categories descriptively below and refer to Table 3 when giving examples:

Content in the category “Action” As definitional content in this category, “administering medications” or “reduction of consciousness” is used as content here with several variations in detail. Using “administering medications” (or similar) renders the definition dependent on one procedure. “Reduction of consciousness”, however, allows different means of sedation, which could, in theory, also be non-medicamentous (e.g. hypnosis with the result of a light and intermittent change in the level of consciousness).

Content in the category “Intention (purpose)” A change in the ‘target’ of the action is stated in this category: for some, it is the perception of the patients [37, 40, 42, 45], for others, it is pain, symptoms or suffering. It is notable that the publication from Austria, where the definition refers to the EAPC definition translates “relieve the burden of otherwise intractable suffering” as “[reduzieren] der Symptomlast in anderweitig therapierefraktären Situationen” [31], meaning “reduce the burden of symptoms in otherwise intractable situations”. In two cases, where an intention was not formulated ([37, 39], cf. Table 3), the means was specified as being ‘adequate for a purpose’ instead. No purpose (and not even this adequacy for a purpose of the means mentioned before) was given at all in two cases [41, 44].

Content in the category “Intended path of action” Some definitions state a purpose and the intended route of accomplishing it (see Table 3). A simplified example would be “administering medications (action) ‘in order to’ relieve suffering (purpose) ‘by’ reduction of consciousness (intended path of action)”. This category is the place to state changes in consciousness (vigilance) when not already stated in the category of action. A basic difference is whether unconsciousness is merely an option (e.g.[24] or logically necessary [46].

Content in the category “Unintended consequence” Here, either exclusiveness of a given purpose is stated [40] or hastening death is excluded as a purpose of the practice [43, 51]. When purposes are excluded, in each case, the relevant passage in the guideline consists of several sentences that might or might not all belong to the definition. Consequently, it is not clear whether the unintended consequence really belongs to the definition. It might also be additional information.

Content in the category “Means” There is considerable variance regarding whether to use this definitional element or not. When used, definitions differ regarding whether to specify medications further up to specific pharmacological classes [46, 51] or to remain unspecific (e.g. “medications”, see Table 3). As mentioned regarding the category “Intention (purpose)”, one noticeable, although rare, strategy is to specify medications concerning their appropriateness for a purpose [37, 39].

Content in the category “Object” Patients and their conditions are described with content in this definitional category. When this category is used, the descriptions range from “merely” an advanced life-limiting illness to imminence of death. It is possible regarding the content in this category to narrow the definition down, for example, to patients with a certain life expectancy. However, we would like to emphasise for better understanding, that not specifying the patient’s condition in the definition at all does not imply permissiveness of the practice for all patients. It merely implies that the ‘designation of the treatment’ does not depend on, for example, life expectancy.

Content in the category “Moral property” Here, the practice, if used at all, is described as morally right for a list of stakeholders, such as patients and relatives. Adding explicit moral evaluations to the definition is a rarely used strategy but, nonetheless, an important one, since it is used by the EAPC and, thus, in all terminological references to the EAPC [27, 31, 40]. The only other publication using content in this category has the same first author [36].

(B) possible contributions of definitions to ‘data problem’ and ‘problem of ethical pre-emption’

Independently of the results in (A) and based on standard from theory of definition [23], we concluded that at least three logically possible ways in which definitions might cause the ‘data problem’ and two possible ways to cause the ‘pre-emption problem’ can be distinguished:

(I) Different definitions: two (or more) different definitions applied to similar cases. If empirical studies use different definitions, then data will probably (though not necessarily) be different. Exemplarily, if the definition used in one study includes intermittent and/or mild sedation while such practices are excluded by the definition in another study, then the frequency reported will differ.

(II) Deviating implicit concepts: one definition, but two (or more) implicit understandings of definitional parts applied to similar cases. This problem can persist ‘even if there is only one operational definition and even if it is precise’. One clinician, for example, might tie the meaning of “palliative sedation” implicitly to deep and continuous sedation of patients until death even if the definition used in the study also includes practices of mild and intermittent sedation.

(III) Disagreement on the facts: one definition but different opinions about the fulfillment of definitional criteria. If one of the definitional criteria is difficult to assess, a matter of feeling or can only be estimated imprecisely, then, as the third possible way, consensus about how to label a case will be difficult to achieve. Thus, labelling might be inconsistent. One example is the use of the criterion “severe suffering”. If two clinicians disagree whether a patient prior to administration of a sedative was “suffering severely”, then they may disagree about whether the case should be labelled as one of “palliative sedation”. Same holds true for “in the last days of life”. Therefore, even if they follow the same and precise definition in a strict way and have the same implicit understanding of the terms, they might label cases differently.

Adding to these ways of causing data problems, at least two ways should be distinguished that might lead to a concern of ethical pre-emption, i.e. concerns about pre-empting critical ethical discussion of the practice by reference to its definition:

(IV) Explicit normativity A definition of sedation in palliative care can be explicitly normative, in the sense that cases are only included that are assessed to be “good practice”. The EAPC definition [15] can be read in such a way. Those who are concerned about bad practice or have a more critical perspective of the practice might find it difficult to even raise their criticism. Their fear (and it might happen) that their concerns are said to be ruled out ‘by definition.’

(V) Implicit normativity A definition is implicitly normative if parts of it are justified by moral arguments. In this way, the scope of the sedation practice is narrowed down indirectly to usage that is deemed to be legitimate. An example is adding “refractory” to the definition, when sedating in situations of ‘non’-refractory symptoms is deemed to be problematic from a moral perspective. Again, critics might find it difficult to formulate their disagreement with the practice when it is implicitly narrowed down to legitimate use.

(C) how content of the definitions contributes to the ‘data’ and ‘pre-emption’ problem in different ways

Having ‘deconstructed’ the definitions in the guidelines, we can link them to the five ways through which the two problems reported (concerning data and ethical pre-emption) might be caused and, thus, bring together results of (A) and (B). In a first step, we demonstrate contributions to the ‘data problem’ and in a second step, contributions to the ‘problem of ethical pre-emption’.

How guideline definitions contribute to the ‘data problem’

Possible contributions by the category “Action”

At first sight, content here can reduce the problem of disagreement about the facts (III) by clarifying what is done. “Reduction of consciousness”, as one possible content in this category, however, might require specification of depth (i.e. deep, mild) and mode (i.e. intermittent, continuous). This may also result in a specification of subtypes of the defined practice. Otherwise – a problem of deviating implicit concepts (II) – different types of sedation might be conflated. In addition, content in this category can generate disagreement about the facts (III). One example would be a clinical situation in which there is doubt whether a “reduction of consciousness” was a result of medication or the consequence of the natural course of disease.

Possible contributions by the category “Intention (purpose)”

Defining by intention has been suggested as the main cause of conceptual confusion [8, 55]. However, it should be noted that “intention” can be understood in at least two ways: ‘psychologically’, “intention” refers to a state of mind; ‘pragmatically’, it refers to features of the treatment. Understood psychologically, intentions are controversially discussed [9, p. 428f.], [56], since agreement about the intentions involved might be difficult to achieve and disagreement about the facts (III) might be the consequence. In the second (pragmatic) meaning it is understood that the intention is independent of the state of mind as long as the actions carried out are the ones one ‘would have chosen if’ one followed the intention. One example of making use of this understanding of intention is the distinction of euthanasia from sedation practices with reference to a specific pattern of practice: “The difference hinges upon whether or not the medications are being titrated to effect. […] If you are titrating to comfort, you are not intending the patient’s death” [57, p. 59].

Empirical reports of mixed and problematic intentions, for example, self-reported intentions of physicians to hasten death when performing sedation [58, p. 182], should only cause conceptual concerns when “intention” is understood psychologically. Therefore, distinguishing the two concepts of intention is important. Using one concept in one situation and the other one in the next might result in data problems via deviating implicit concepts (II).

The targets of the practice stated in this category often include refractoriness. This content of the definitional cetegory is prone to disagreement about the facts (III), since refractoriness might be assessed controversially in a clinical situation. The same holds true for the decision on whether suffering is “unbearable” [28, 29, 36, 38, 42, 47, 48, 51].

Possible contributions by the category “Intended path of action”

The intention here can also be interpreted psychologically or pragmatically, with the same possible effects. Has the path to be present “mentally” or does it depend on the specific clinical actions carried out?

Possible contributions by the category “Non-intendend consequences”

Again, all comments regarding “intention” also generally apply here. Assume, for example, that hastening death is explicitly excluded as a purpose [51]. Then, in cases where clinicians accepted or would have appreciated a life-shortening effect, they might consider this part of the definition as not fulfilled (psychological interpretation) or, nonetheless, fulfilled (pragmatic) when treatment was carried out properly. Mixing psychological and pragmatic readings will result in deviating implicit concepts (II). Psychological meaning will probably lead to disagreement about the facts (III), since intentions have many facets psychologically that hamper simple agreement on who had which intentions [56].

Possible contributions by the category “Means”

Using content in the definition that specifies the means can have the result that the defined practice becomes outdated “technologically”, at least in principle. For sedation practice this might happen when interventions other than pharmacological ones become plausible means. This could result in different definitions (I) in study comparison. However, this risk is currently low, since only hypnosis is the other intervention candidate and, so far, only at the lower end of the spectrum of sedative effects (mild and intermittent).

The same seems to hold true for deviating implicit concepts (II): as long as interventions are almost exclusively pharmacological, the risk of implicit different interpretations is low. However, the risk increases with formulations that might be interpreted as different classes of substances by different interpreters. Do “sedatives”, for example, include opiates because of their sedative effect in higher dosages or only medications that are approbated primarily for their sedative effects, such as benzodiazepines and anaesthetics? Implicit deviations influencing quantitative data might be a result.

Possible contributions by the category “Object”

This category brings a high risk of all types of causes of data problems, since it specifies the patients treated. First of all, and obviously: studies limited to a specific patient population should not be compared with studies that did not specify patient condition or specified it differently, because they use different definitions. This includes especially definitional content specifying life expectancy [24, 26, 28, 29, 34, 36, 41, 43, 44, 46, 47, 51].

Great attention should be paid to deviating implicit concepts (II): even if the definition is well-made and precise, it is easy to imagine that patients are included in statistical analysis who violate the definition (e.g. a patient with unclear or longer life prognosis in a clinical crisis). Much depends on whether those who “apply” the definition treat information about patient condition as a strict inclusion criterion or as a noncommittal description of “typical” patients.

Disagreement on the facts (III) is to be expected, since typical content in this category, such as life expectancy, is not easy to assess. The assessment of identical cases might vary between practitioners and wards, with varying labelling of cases and, thus, varying statistical reports.

Possible contributions by the category “Moral properties”

Adding content here can pose challenges for research because it is likely that there will be different moral evaluations of a specific case and, thus, disagreement about the facts (III) – in this case, on the moral value of the measure. There might, for example, be disagreement about whether sedation was indeed acceptable for the family of the patient. Moreover, a definition encompassing a moral property cannot be used to operationalise the object of a study when the study’s goal is to survey a range of practices broadly. This is because the use of the category automatically narrows the ranges of practices elicited down to those deemed to be morally acceptable. Only cases which are in line with the ethical requirements would be included. Not paying attention to this logical consequence could result in different definitions (I) in study comparison.

Results concerning the ‘problem of ethical pre-emption’

Possible contributions by normativity of definitional content

Regarding implicit normativity (as defined above), we see issues of perspective on and “handling” of definitions rather than a problem of specific definitional content. Content in all categories can be seen as implicitly normative: use of the respective category and decision regarding a specific content might be motivated by ethical considerations. As an example, “monitoring” or “medications” as a means [15] is stated because it is considered to be the state-of-the-art of ethical practice to only use medication or to monitor patients.

Based on our analysis, we conclude that this is the case for content in every category. Obvious examples are definitional contents regarding intractability of symptoms, explicit formulations of life expectancy or unintended consequences. Such content can be found in all guideline definitions, even in those which are intentionally formulated in a more “descriptive” way. Why, for example, does the guideline definition from the Netherlands include “in the last stage of life” in its definition [44, 59]? It is because the committee holds sedation for symptom control to be ‘acceptable’ under this (vague) condition: “Lowering the patient’s consciousness to relieve suffering is appropriate in the last stages of life, in which death is expected to ensue in the near future” [44, p. 19]. One purpose of choosing a definition thus seems to be to express the ethical considerations in the guideline regarding good practice.

As an example, the definition in the EAPC guideline would, in this respect, not be intended to “neutrally” describe the practice to be regulated with the guideline. Instead, the clinical activity to be regulated, is – as stated in the title – “the use of sedation in palliative care”. Accordingly, the document is the result of the EAPC’s considerations about rules of good practice for this activity. Parts of these considerations are summarised and expressed in a definition of a specific medical practice termed “palliative (or therapeutic) sedation”. We do not see how any normativity would, in fact, imply a ‘problem of ethical pre-emption’ that requires solutions when this is considered. However, it is important to be able to formulate ethical concerns about a practice. We will discuss strategies to accomplish this below.

Discussion

The preceding analyses indicate that common ground regarding definitions of sedation in palliative care is small. In fact, “reduced consciousness” (or similar) is the only content shared by all definitions analysed. This finding contrasts with the statement in the latest systematic review on guidelines, according to which “Palliative sedation was defined in analogous ways in all guidelines, that is, as an intervention instituted solely for the purpose of refractory symptom control” [60, p. 225]. However, as shown in our analysis, stating an intention does not form part of all guideline definitions. In addition, guidelines often refer to the relieving of “suffering” but not of “symptoms” and rarely exclude purposes explicitly.

As our results show, search for a ‘point of convergence’ of definitions won’t lead to well-build terminology. Because of that we suggest options for systematic conceptual improvement in the following and no statistical argument (‘The more often used, the better the definition’).

Improving in light of the ‘data problem’

Revisiting different definitions (I) as the first possible cause of the ‘data problem’, an obvious solution is the use of only one precise definition in a study. This becomes even more important in study comparison. Thus, respective publications should provide detailed information about the types of sedation (i.e. mode and depth) included and all other exclusion and inclusion criteria. This could relieve a considerable part of the uncertainty and would be in line with repeated pleas to solve existing inconsistencies by uniform definitions [61, p. 310] or by defining subcate- gories of a broad definition [62, p. 447].

A clearer picture of the definitional elements that should be used and reported as part of the research can be achieved by considering strategies regarding the two other possible ways to cause the ‘data problem’. Concerning deviating implicit concepts (II), improvement seems possible by providing definitions of the defining terms or by adding clarifying comments. One possible improvement (for the category of “Intended path of action”) would be defining “reduced consciousness” explicitly. This could be done by using scales, such as RASS [63], RASS-PAL [64] or other assessment techniques. A second option (to clarify the category of “moral properties”) would be handing out additional information on what is meant by “ethically acceptable” to guide on the relevance of ethical evaluation. Thirdly, regarding the formulation of means, pharmacological accuracy is needed (e.g. specify “sedative” [32, 36, 39, 49, 50]). A fourth option to reduce deviating implicit concepts would be to clarify the category of “object”. One might clarify, for example, “terminally ill patients” by pointing out that this covers patients with a prognosis of a maximum of 14 days according to the treating physician. One additional chance is to clarify the meaning of the category “intention” – if it is used as part of the definition at all. In this respect, the definitions from Spain and Belgium [37, 39] are examples of how to express a clearly “pragmatic” understanding of intention, e.g. “sedatives in dosages [dots] required to reduce the consciousness […] as much as needed to control one or more refractory symptoms in an adequate manner” [39] (our emphasis).

One tool that can be utilised as a strategy to identify implicit concepts can be cognitive interviews with participating researchers to identify their implicit (mis)understandings of a definition before using it [65]. Such interviews could be informed by our analysis of definitional categories.

Concerning the third way to cause the ‘data problem’ disagreement about the facts (III), our analysis shows that several expressions are particularly prone to such a challenge, but for different reasons. One source can be areas in which it is known that professional judgments are uncertain and differ, for example, concerning the prognosis of life expectancy in the category of object or intractability in the category of purpose. Another reason for disagreement about facts are judgments about mental states involved in “unbearable suffering” and in the category of purpose. In addition, formulations of ethical properties are prone to disagreement about facts due to moral pluralism in societies. Identifying and discarding those elements from the definition that are prone to disagreement should be considered.

A systematically constructed new proposal of terminology is beyond the scope of this article. Nevertheless, answering the following question should improve the terminological quality of future definitions:

  1. 1

    Have you discussed each definitional element for implications and alternative formulations?

  2. 2

    Is the definitional element necessary and have you relocated nice-to-have information to supplementary material?

  3. 3

    Can you be sure that readers interpret the definition consistently? If not, can you improve this by reformulation or supplementary information?

  4. 4

    Have you minimised the risk of disagreement about facts for each category?

  5. 5

    Have you tested the reliability of the definition?

One promising option in the context of guidelines can be refraining from the definition of the good practice measure in favour of a precise definition of “sedation”, accompanied by rules of good practice for “sedation in palliative care” – not because of concerns about pre-emption but for the goal of avoiding confusion, implicit assumptions and unsound data. Assessing the pros and cons of this option requires interdisciplinary research, which, in addition to conceptual analyses, should also include empirical (qualitative) data on the use of concepts of sedation, misunderstandings and associations, as well as legal requirements for definitions.

Improving in light of the ‘problem of ethical preemption’

Our analyses indicate that some elements of the definitions are obviously the result of ethical considerations about due care. There is no ‘problem of ethical pre-emption’ when discourse partners accept this and argue accordingly.

Distinguishing the purpose of a definition in a guideline from the purpose of a definition that responds to requirements of empirical research is important to reduce the current confusion in palliative sedation discourse. A possible (though not necessary) requirement for research purposes is that the definition covers a wide scope of practices, regardless of whether they fit an ideal of good practice. By contrast, a definition of a practice in a guideline often (though not necessarily) focuses on normative criteria which automatically limit its scope. Against this background, the use of guideline definitions in empirical work which aims to explore sedation practices generally often seems ill-informed. Moreover, distinguishing purposes of definitions solves the ‘problem of ethical pre-emption’ mentioned above, since it makes explicit that a guideline definition often does not serve the purpose of describing a practice but often aims to express a regulated practice. The use of positive moral aspects in a definition of sedation practices has even been called “intellectually dishonest”[9, p. 429]. Unsurprisingly, the authors attacked responded stridently [66, p. e11 f.]. Such a general discussion about neutrality or normativity of definitions without recognising different purposes of definitions seems pointless to us.

Instead, ethical concerns regarding, for example, indications, motivation and medications used [1] can all be formulated referring to the use of ‘sedation in palliative care’ – regardless of the definitions in guidelines. Conversely, criticism of the practice or regulations of ‘sedation in palliative care’ cannot be answered by referring to a definition.

Limitations

The systematic literature search has some limitations and a possible bias towards English speaking countries. Potential further publications not written or tagged in English might reveal additional definitional strategies. The same might be true for legal documents, palliative care text books or single hospital documents. Interpretative misunderstandings during extraction and translation of the definitions might are also possible. As mentioned above, we had to interpret passages of some publications to identify a definition. This may have influenced our analysis. It also indicates though, that core terminology should be easier to identify in guidelines.

Conclusion

There is a lack of consensus and a high potential even for different kinds of confusion regarding the labeling of sedation practices in palliative care. Separate solution strategies can be formulated for these different kinds of problems. Calling for uniformity of definitions alone, without an understanding of the underlying types of problems, will not help to improve the conceptual situation concerning sedation in palliative care. Instead, the categories presented and our analyses of impact on conceptual problems in different ways can serve as a starting point when constructing terminology. They can guide reflection on the intuitive use of terms and be used to explore whether concepts are confused in communication in research or everyday practice. In addition, our methodological distinction of different purposes of the definition and implications may further the dissent on pre-emption of the ethical dispute about sedation practices in palliative care.

Availability of data and materials

Exact search strategy and initial search results of the systematic literature search can be obtained from the authors.

References

  1. Twycross R. Reflections on palliative sedation. Palliat Care Res Treat. 2019; 12:1–16. https://doi.org/10.1177/1178224218823511.

    Google Scholar 

  2. Rietjens JAC, van Delden JJM, van der Heide A. Palliative sedation: The end of heated debate?Palliat Med. 2018; 32(11):1639–40.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  3. Rodrigues P, Crokaert J, Gastmans C. Palliative sedation for existential suffering: a systematic review of argument-based ethics literature. J Pain Symptom Manag. 2018; 55(6):1577–90.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  4. Sulmasy DP. Sedation and care at the end of life. Theor Med Bioeth. 2018; 39(3):171–80.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  5. Schildmann E, Schildmann J. Palliative sedation therapy: a systematic literature review and critical appraisal of available guidance on indication and decision making. J Palliat Med. 2014; 17(5):601–11.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  6. Papavasiliou ES, Brearley SG, Seymour JE, Brown J, Payne SA. From sedation to continuous sedation until death: how has the conceptual basis of sedation in end-of-life care changed over time?J Pain Symptom Manag. 2013; 46(5):691–706.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  7. Rys S, Mortier F, Deliens L, Dschepper R, Battin MP, Bilsen J. Continuous sedation until death: moral justifications of physicians and nurses–a content analysis of opinion pieces. Med Health Care Philos. 2013; 16(3):533–42.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  8. Morita T, Imai K, Yokomichi N, Mori M, Kizawa Y, Tsuneto S. Continuous deep sedation: a proposal for performing more rigorous empirical research. J Pain Symptom Manag. 2017; 53(1):146–52.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  9. Raus K, Sterckx S. How defining clinical practices may influence their evaluation: the case of continuous sedation at the end of life. J Eval Clin Pract. 2016; 22(3):425–32.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  10. Schur S, Weixler D, Gabl C, Kreye G, Likar R, Masel EK, Mayrhofer M, Reiner F, Schmidmayr B, Kirchheiner K, et al. Sedation at the end of life - a nation-wide study in palliative care units in Austria. BMC Palliat Care. 2016; 15(1):50.

    Article  PubMed  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

  11. Schildmann E, Pörnbacher S, Kalies H, Bausewein C. ‘Palliative sedation’? A retrospective cohort study on the use and labelling of continuously administered sedatives on a palliative care unit. Palliat Med. 2018; 32(7):1189–97.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  12. Stiel S, Nurnus M, Ostgathe C, Klein C. Palliative sedation in Germany: factors and treatment practices associated with different sedation rate estimates in palliative and hospice care services. BMC Palliat Care. 2018; 17(1):48.

    Article  PubMed  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

  13. Seymour J, Rietjens J, Brown J, van der Heide A, Sterckx S, Deliens L. The perspectives of clinical staff and bereaved informal care-givers on the use of continuous sedation until death for cancer patients: The study protocol of the UNBIASED study. BMC Palliat Care. 2011; 10(1):1–8.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  14. Rietjens JAC, van Tol DG, Schermer M, van der Heide A. Judgement of suffering in the case of a euthanasia request in The Netherlands. J Med Ethics. 2009; 35(8):502–7.

    Article  CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  15. Cherny NI, Radbruch L. European Association for Palliative Care (EAPC) recommended framework for the use of sedation in palliative care. Palliat Med. 2009; 23(7):581–93.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  16. Carnap R. Logical foundations of probability, 2nd ed. Chicago: Univ. of Chicago Press; 1951.

    Google Scholar 

  17. Siegwart G. Explikation In: Löffler W, Runggaldier E, editors. Dialog und System. Otto Muck zum 65. Geburtstag. Sankt Augustin: Academia: 1997. p. 15–45.

    Google Scholar 

  18. Siegwart G, zur Wahrheit V. Scientia Nova. München: Oldenbourg; 1997.

    Google Scholar 

  19. Cordes M, Siegwart G. Explication In: Fieser J, Dowden B, editors. Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy: 2018. https://www.iep.utm.edu/explicat/. Accessed 1 June 2020.

  20. Moher D, Liberati A, Tetzlaff J, Altman DG, Prisma Group. Preferred reporting items for systematic reviews and meta-analyses: the PRISMA statement. PLOS Med. 2009; 6(7):1–6. https://doi.org/10.1371/journal.pmed.1000097.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  21. Brouwers MC, Kho ME, Browman GP, Burgers JS, Cluzeau F, Feder G, Fervers B, Graham ID, Grimshaw J, Hanna SE, et al. AGREE II: advancing guideline development, reporting and evaluation in health care. Can Med Assoc J. 2010; 182(839–42).

  22. Wright GHv. Explanation and understanding: Cornell University Press; 2004.

  23. Suppes P. Theory of Definition. In: Introduction to Logic. New York: van Nostrand Reinhold: 1957. p. 151–73.

    Google Scholar 

  24. Force PSTTask. The Waterloo Wellington Palliative Sedation Therapy Protocol. 2019. https://wwpalliativecare.ca/Uploads/ContentDocuments/20191220_WW_PST_Final.pdf. Accessed 1 June 2020.

  25. Care pathway guide. How to implement continuous deep sedation until death? 2018. https://www.has-sante.fr/upload/docs/application/pdf/2018-11/care_pathway_guide_how_to_implement_continuous_deep_sedation_until_death.pdf. Accessed 1 June 2020.

  26. Provincial Clinical Knowledge Topic. Palliative Sedation, Adult – All Locations V 1.0. 2018. https://extranet.ahsnet.ca/teams/policydocuments/1/klink/et-klink-ckv-palliative-sedation-adult-all-locations.pdf. Accessed 1 June 2020.

  27. Rice J, Graves E, Howard S, Lalumière G, Malinowski J, Splinter J, Valk N, Barkley W, DaPonte M, Skinner E, Tierney S. The Champlain Region Palliative Sedation Therapy Clinical Practice and Medication Guidelines. 2018. https://champlainpalliative.ca/wp-content/uploads/2018/10/PST-Guidelines-Regional-2018_ENG-final.pdf. Accessed 1 June 2020.

  28. Harlos M, Empleton L, Barlas J, Browning J, Crawford G, Dunsford J, et al. Sedation for Palliative Purposes Guideline. 2017. http://www.wrha.mb.ca/extranet/eipt/files/EIPT-045.pdf. Accessed 1 June 2020.

  29. British Columbia Centre for Palliative Care. Refractory symptoms and palliative sedation. 2017. https://www.bc-cpc.ca/cpc/wp-content/uploads/2019/06/17-RefractorySymptomsAndPalliativeSedationColourPrint.pdf. Accessed 1 June 2020.

  30. The Australian and New Zealand Society of Palliative Medicine. Palliative Sedation Therapy. Guidance Document. 2017. http://www.anzspm.org.au/c/anzspm?a=sendfile&ft=p&fid=1587788353&sid=. Accessed 1 June 2020.

  31. Weixler D, Roider-Schur S, Likar R, Bozzaro C, Daniczek T, Feichtner A, Gabl C, Hammerl-Ferrari B, Kletecka-Pulker M, Körtner UHJ, Kössler H, Meran JG, Miksovsky A, Pusswald B, Wienerroither T, Watzke H. Leitlinie zur Palliativen Sedierungstherapie (Langversion). Wien Med Wochenschr. 2017; 167(1):31–48.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  32. Azzaria S, Nickner G, Carrier R, Côté A, Dallaire MM, Dechêne G, et al. Societé québécoise des médecins de soins palliatifś; College des médecins du Québec̀. Palliative sedation for adults: Principles and best practices. Guidelines proposed by the SQMDSP. Med Palliat. 2016; 14(6):360–82. http://www.cmq.org/publications-pdf/p-1-2016-08-29-en-sedation-palliative-fin-de-vie.pdf. Accessed 1 June 2020.

    Google Scholar 

  33. UCLA Health. Administration of palliative sedation to the dying patient. 2015. https://www.pcqn.org/wp-content/uploads/2017/04/UCLA-Palliative-Sedation-policy.pdf. Accessed 1 June 2020.

  34. Practice Development and Quality Committee. Palliative Sedation Guideline. 2015. http://www.cspcp.ca/wp-content/uploads/2017/11/Palliative-Sedation-Edmonton-Final-Dec-2015.pdf. Accessed 1 June 2020.

  35. The Norwegian Medical Association. Guidelines for palliative sedation at the end of life. 2014. https://www.legeforeningen.no/contentassets/cc8a35f6afd043c195ede88a15ae2960/guidelines-for-palliative-sedation-at-the-end-of-life.pdf. Accessed 1 June 2020.

  36. Cherny NI. ESMO Clinical Practice Guidelines for the management of refractory symptoms at the end of life and the use of palliative sedation. Ann Oncol. 2014; 25:143–52. doi:10.1093/annonc/mdu238.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  37. Organización Médica Colegial de España and Sociedad Española de Cuidados Paliativos. Guía de sédacion paliativa. 2012. https://www.cgcom.es/sites/default/files/guia_sedaccion_paliativa.pdf. Accessed 1 June 2020.

  38. Dean MM, Cellarius V, Henry B, Oneschuk D. Librach Canadian Society Of Palliative Care Physicians Taskforce SL. Framework for continuous palliative sedation therapy in Canada. J Palliat Med. 2012; 15(8):870–9.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  39. Broeckaert B, Mullie A, Gielen J, Desmet M, Declerck D, Vanden Berghe P. Palliatieve Sedatie. Richtlijn, Versie 2.0. 2012. http://www.pallialine.be/accounts/129/docs/richtlijn_palliatieve_sedatie.pdf. Accessed 1 June 2020.

  40. Irish Association for Palliative Care. Palliative Sedation. Discussion Paper. 2011. http://www.iapc.ie/iapc-publications/palliative-sedation-discussion-paper/. Accessed 1 June 2020.

  41. Dyson T, Kennedy B, Macpherson N, Roberts; Fraser Health Authority. Refractory symptoms and palliative sedation therapy. Hosp Palliat Care Prog symptoms Guidel. 2011. https://www.fraserhealth.ca/-/media/Project/FraserHealth/FraserHealth/Health-Professionals/Professionals-Resources/Hospice-palliative-care/Sections-PDFs-for-FH-Aug31/9524-28-FH---Sym_Guide-RefractoryPalliativeSedation.pdf. Accessed 1 June 2020.

  42. Kirk TW, Mahon MM, Palliative Sedation Task Force of the National Hospice and Palliative Care Organization Ethics Committee. National Hospice and Palliative Care Organization (NHPCO) position statement and commentary on the use of palliative sedation in imminently dying terminally ill patients. J Pain Symptom Manag. 2010; 39(5):914–23. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.jpainsymman.2010.01.009.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  43. Etiska riktlinjer för palliativ sedering i livets slutskede. 2010. http://www.sls.se/PageFiles/225/000012134pdf. Accessed 1 June 2020.

  44. Royal Dutch Medical Association (KNMG). Guideline for Palliative Sedation. 2009. https://www.palliativedrugs.com/download/091110_KNMG_Guideline_for_Palliative_sedation_2009__2_%5B1%5D.pdf. Accessed 1 June 2020.

  45. Sédation pour détresse terminale et Sédation pour détresse en en phase phase terminale et dans des situations spécifiques et complexes. 2009. http://www.sfap.org/system/files/sedation-phase-terminale.pdf. Accessed 1 June 2020.

  46. National Ethics Committee, Veterans Health Administration. The ethics of palliative sedation as a therapy of last resort. Am J Hosp Palliat Med. 2007; 23(6):483–91.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  47. SICP. Raccomandazioni della SICP sulla Sedazione Terminale/Sedazione Palliativa. 2007. https://www.sicp.it/wp-content/uploads/2018/12/7_Sedazione.pdf. Accessed 1 June 2020.

  48. Bonito V, Caraceni A, Borghi L, Marcello N, Mori M, Porteri C, Casella G, Causarano R, Gasparini M, Colombi L, Defanti CA, SIN Bioethics and Palliative Care Study Group. The clinical and ethical appropriateness of sedation in palliative neurological treatments. Neurol Sciences Off J Ital Neurol Soc Ital Soc Clin Neurophysiol. 2005; 26(5):370–85. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10072-005-0503-9. https://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pubmed/16388377.

    CAS  Google Scholar 

  49. BIGORIO. Empfehlungen Palliative Sedation. 2005. https://www.palliative.ch/fileadmin/user_upload/palliative/fachwelt/E_Standards/E_12_3_bigorio_2006_Sedation_de.pdf. Accessed 1 June 2020.

  50. Morita T, Bito S, Kurihara Y, Uchitomi Y. Development of a clinical guideline for palliative sedation therapy using the Delphi method. J Palliat Med. 2005; 8(4):716–29.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  51. Pace C, Abrahm J, Ward A, Fontaine K, Twyeffort L, Schutt C. Palliative Sedation Protocol. Massachusetts. 2004. https://cdn.ymaws.com/www.hospicefed.org/resource/resmgr/hpcfm_pdf_doc/pal_sed_protocol_2004.pdf. Accessed 1 June 2020.

  52. Oechsle K, Radbruch L, Wolf C, Ostgathe C. SOP–Palliative Sedierung. Der Onkologe. 2017; 23(6):469–75.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  53. Sánchez MA, Cuervo MA, Sánchez R, Varillas MP, Hernández P, Encinas P, et al. Guía Clímica. Sedación paliativa del prcpex. 2014. https://saludextremadura.ses.es/filescms/paliex/uploaded_files/guia-de-sedacion.pdf. Accessed 1 June 2020.

  54. Japanese Guideline on Sedation. Available from: https://www.jspm.ne.jp/guidelines/sedation/sedation01.pdf. Accessed 1 June 2020.

  55. Morita T, Maeda I, Mori M, Imai K, Tsuneto S. Uniform definition of continuous-deep sedation. Lancet Oncol. 2016; 17(6):e222.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  56. Quill T. The Ambiguity of Clinical Intentions. N Engl J Med. 1993; 329(14):1039–40.

    Article  CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  57. Krakauer EL, Penson RT, Truog RD, King LA, Chabner BA, Lynch Jr TJ. Sedation for intractable distress of a dying patient: acute palliative care and the principle of double effect. The Oncologist. 2000; 5(1):53–62.

    Article  CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  58. Rietjens JAC, van der Heide A, Vrakking AM, Onwuteaka-Philipsen BD, van der Maas PJ, van der Wal Gerrit. Physician reports of terminal sedation without hydration or nutrition for patients nearing death in the Netherlands. Ann Intern Med. 2004; 141(3):178–85.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  59. Rietjens J, van Delden H, Deliens L, van der Heide A. Re: Palliative sedation: the need for a descriptive definition. J Pain Symptom Manag. 2009; 37(3):10–1.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  60. Abarshi E, Rietjens J, Robijn L, Caraceni A, Payne S, Deliens L, Van den Block L. International variations in clinical practice guidelines for palliative sedation: a systematic review. BMJ Support Palliat Care. 2017; 7(3):223–9. https://doi.org/10.1136/bmjspcare-2016-001159. http://spcare.bmj.com/content/7/3/223.

    PubMed  Google Scholar 

  61. Claessens P, Menten J, Schotsmans P, Broeckaert B. Palliative sedation: A review of the research literature. J Pain Symptom Manag. 2008; 36(3):310–33. doi:10.1016/j.jpainsymman.2007.10.004.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  62. Morita T, Tsuneto S, Shima Y. Proposed definitions for terminal sedation. The Lancet. 2001; 358(9278):335–6.

    Article  CAS  Google Scholar 

  63. Sessler CN, Grap MJ, Brophy GM. Multidisciplinary management of sedation and analgesia in critical care. Semin Respir Crit Care Med. 2001; 22:211–26.

    Article  CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  64. Bush SH, Grassau PA, Yarmo MN, Zhang T, Zinkie SJ, Pereira JL. The Richmond Agitation-Sedation Scale modified for palliative care inpatients (RASS-PAL): a pilot study exploring validity and feasibility in clinical practice. BMC Palliat Care. 2014; 13(1):17.

    Article  PubMed  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

  65. Prüfer P, Rexroth M. Zwei-Phasen-Pretesting. ZUMA-Arbeitsbericht 2000/08. Mannheim: ZUMA. 2000. https://nbn-resolving.org/urn:nbn:de:0168-ssoar-200864. Accessed 1 June 2020.

  66. Broeckaert B, Claessens P, Menten J, Schotsmans P. Authors’ Reply: A Descriptive Definition of Palliative Sedation?J Pain Symptom Manag. 2009; 37(3):e11–2.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

We would like to thank R. Voss for her assistance in the systematic literature search, S. Nadolny for further support, G. Siegwart for helpful suggestions concerning definition and explication and all members of the research project “SedPall” for their feedback on earlier versions of the paper. We would also like to thank the reviewers for providing helpful comments on an earlier version of the paper.

Funding

This research has been conducted within the research project “Sedation within specialized palliative care – concepts and empirico-ethical analysis of the current practice in Germany” (SedPall), funded by the German Federal Ministry of Education and Research (01GY1702A-C). The funder finances the position of the first author and workshops related to the topic. The funder did not influence content or methods of this study.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Contributions

AK developed the action-theoretic analytical scheme, analysed and translated the guideline definitions. AK and JS wrote and revised the article and both read and approved the final manuscript.

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Alexander Kremling.

Ethics declarations

Ethics approval and consent to participate

Not applicable.

Consent for publication

Not applicable.

Competing interests

The authors declare that they have no competing interests.

Additional information

Publisher’s Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Additional material

Additional file 1

PRISMA Flow diagram.

Additional file 2

PRISMA checklist.

Additional file 3

Extracted definitions with deconstruction of content, sorted by year of publication (* = our translation)

Rights and permissions

Open Access This article is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 International License, which permits use, sharing, adaptation, distribution and reproduction in any medium or format, as long as you give appropriate credit to the original author(s) and the source, provide a link to the Creative Commons licence, and indicate if changes were made. The images or other third party material in this article are included in the article’s Creative Commons licence, unless indicated otherwise in a credit line to the material. If material is not included in the article’s Creative Commons licence and your intended use is not permitted by statutory regulation or exceeds the permitted use, you will need to obtain permission directly from the copyright holder. To view a copy of this licence, visit http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/. The Creative Commons Public Domain Dedication waiver (http://creativecommons.org/publicdomain/zero/1.0/) applies to the data made available in this article, unless otherwise stated in a credit line to the data.

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Kremling, A., Schildmann, J. What do you mean by “palliative sedation”?. BMC Palliat Care 19, 147 (2020). https://doi.org/10.1186/s12904-020-00635-9

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1186/s12904-020-00635-9

Keywords